複製或不複製?——基因複製的倫理震撼

To Clone or Not to Clone: The Moral Challenges of Human Cloning

Authors

  • 江丕盛 (Phee Seng KANG) 香港浸會大學 (Hong Kong Baptist University, HONG KONG)

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.24112/ijccpm.11343

Keywords:

複製人, 基因複製, 無性生殖, 有性生殖, 體胞核移植法, 身分, 基因決定論, 同卵雙胞胎, 「我-你」, 位格成長, 兩性契合, 物化, 商品化, 基因複製權, 生殖權

Abstract

LANGUAGE NOTE | Document text in Chinese; abstract also in English.

複製人實質上就是複製活過或仍活著的人的基因組合。本文嘗試就下列五方面探討體胞核移植法在人類身上的應用所引起的社會倫理問題。

(一)基因等同:兩個人是否可以共有同一基因組合?

(二)基因歷史:複製者的基因並非是一個新的、獨特的基因組合。這基因曾有的(即被複製者的)歷史對複製者是否有負面影響?

(三)基因傳遞方式:無性生殖方式的基因傳遞對複製者是否有負面影響?

(四)基因複製風險:複製帶給複製者什麼風險?

(五)基因複製權:基因複製權衍生出什麼倫理問題?

對全面支持複製科技在人類的應用的論者來說,複製只是另類生殖方法,提供人多一個生殖途徑的選擇。複製對他人並無傷害,對社會沒有負面影響。既或有任何傷害或影響,也都是可以接受的。因此,在一般的情況下,複製人科技不應該遭受社會的禁止。

本文的討論顯示這是過度樂觀的看法。以「基因複製產生身分混淆」的反對說法固然不成立。然而,基因通往的歷史,無性生殖的方式,複製初階的風險,以及棘手的基因複製法律問題及由此再衍生的倫理問題等,這些對複製孩子,人倫關係,家庭結構及社會穩定所可能造成的負面衝擊和嚴重傷害是不容忽視的。複製人科技即使可行,也應該在極嚴格的監管下進行。

更重要的是,複製人的社會倫理震撼是國際社會的共同關注。因此,複製人的支持者必須對國際社會的深切關注與廣泛責難提供強而有力的證據與回應。在國際社會對複製人仍有極大疑慮時即勿促容許複製人的出現,肯定是極不負責任的做法。

To clone or not to clone? Having successfully cloned animals, should we clone human beings or should we ban human cloning? This paper explores some ethical concerns brought on by the possibility of human cloning. The cloning specifically referred to here is the asexual reproduction of a human by somatic cell nuclear transfer.

Five concerns are discussed. The first is genetic equivalence and identity. The second is genetic history and individual autonomy. The third is asexual reproduction. The fourth is experimentation risks. The fifth is cloning rights.

Genetic-Cloning not Person-Cloning

One main objection to human cloning arises from equating genetic reproduction with person reproduction. Because the clone derives his genes from the cloned, it is feared that cloning will make carbon copies of people. Although genetic reproduction will produce clones that resemble the cloned biologically, the two are different persons just as monozygotic twins are. External factors such as the environment, experiences and culture also shape a person. Human cloning will not call back the dead nor immortalise the living. It is in fact genetic cloning but never person cloning. It is not achievement cloning nor virtue cloning. The objection is based on genetic reductionism.

Genes with a History

Human cloning is sometimes equated with producing monozygotic twins. However the two are not the same because of the significant age difference between the clone and its cloned. Although identical twins share the same genes, their development is an unknown and full of possibilities as is the case for all newborn. Their future is open because their genetic make-up is, practically speaking, unique. However, in the case of the clone, its genes have a known history. The pre-existence of the genes will assert itself on the clone in one way or another. In the first place, the clone's corning into existence was not 'spontaneous' nor 'open' as in newborn by birth. It cannot claim as other humans can: "I am me." The clone is created in the image of the cloned and inevitably lives in its shadow. Its identity is being infringed upon by the history of its genes.

The pre-existence of the genes also constitutes a violation of the privacy of the clone. Because the cloned has lived before it, the secrets of the clone's genes are opened for all to see. The clone of Stephen Hawking would thus lose its genetic confidentially if he had cloned himself at the age of twenty before knowing his genetic problem. His clone will be what he is twenty years later.

The pre-existence of the genes also renders possible their commodification or commercialisation.

Asexual Reproduction

In nature's way, the inception of a new life occurs in the embrace and sexual union of man and woman, which is the culmination of the love between them. The new life is conceived and born out of an I-Thou relationship of love and commitment. The clone in an asexual reproduction is a product of technology rather than a gift within personal union. It is deprived of its right to having a biological father and a biological mother.

Moreover, cloning also assaults the traditional concept of parenthood and radically threatens the stability of family.

Cloning Risks

The high failure rate in cloning Dolly indicates clearly the much higher risks involved in human cloning. Malformed embryos will be produced and destroyed under current practice.

Malformed embryos have been inadequately justified by the proponents of human cloning on three grounds: that there are always unavoidable experimentation failures, that there are also risks in normal pregnancies and that the embryos have no moral rights before coming into existence. These justifications are found to be wanting. Moreover, to many who advocate respect for Iife, including the life of embryos, it is morally wrong to destroy embryos.

Furthermore there is the risk of malformed clones even though its can be reduced by the destruction of malformed embryos. The defects number of cloning are not fully known until years later or even a generation later. In the early stage of cloning development the clones remain objects of experiment throughout their entire lives. They have to live always under the threat of some possible adverse effect of cloning. This is morally unacceptable.

Cloning Rights

The issue of cloning rights can be complicated. Who has the right to cloning? Do parents have the right to clone a child? Will they only be able to exercise the right jointly or can they do so seperately? What happens when they are divorced? Will they forfeit this right when the child comes of age? Who owns the frozen embryo cloned earlier? Will the parents' right be an infringement on the person's right? Can they stop her from cloning herself? Can one clone more than a dozen of oneself? Does the right to clone entail patent right? Is the right to clone transferable or tradable?

It has often been assumed that the decision of cloning is entirely the parents' as the clone before coming into existence has no moral status. However in the case of cloning a child, is it necessary to have the consent of the child even though she is a minor? Are the parents guardians or pirates of her genome?

To Clone or Not to Clone

One must also bear in mind that the concept of reproductive right used by the proponents is very much a western concept and is at best a negative right which should not be placed above the right of the clone.

The answer to the question "To clone or not to clone?" is not a straight forward one. Human cloning will pose challenges in the realms of technology, law, society, morality, philosophy and religion. The most pressing question is not whether there is a case that can be justified for human cloning. It is rather whether our society has enough moral wisdom, courage and strength to guide the development and application of advancing science and technology including the possibility of human cloning. Before we can come to grips with the issues facing us, we should proceed with great care.

DOWNLOAD HISTORY | This article has been downloaded 22 times in Digital Commons before migrating into this platform.

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

Downloads

Published

1998-01-01

How to Cite

KANG, P. S. (1998). 複製或不複製?——基因複製的倫理震撼: To Clone or Not to Clone: The Moral Challenges of Human Cloning. International Journal of Chinese &Amp; Comparative Philosophy of Medicine, 1(3), 95–123. https://doi.org/10.24112/ijccpm.11343

Issue

Section

Articles